Tải bản đầy đủ (.pdf) (16 trang)

A Companion to the History of Economic Thought - Chapter 25 pdf

Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (197.79 KB, 16 trang )

THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 395
CHAPTER TWENTY- FIVE
The Formalist
Revolution of
the 1950s
Mark Blaug
25.1 INTRODUCTION
Something happened to economics in the decade of the 1950s that is little appre-
ciated by most economists and even by professional historians of economic
thought: the subject went through an intellectual revolution as profound in its
impact as the so-called “Keynesian Revolution” of prewar years. I call it the
Formalist Revolution after Ward (1972, pp. 40–1), who was the first to recognize
the enormous intellectual transformation of economics in the years after World
War II.
It is common to think of interwar economics in terms of a struggle between
institutionalists and neoclassicists but, as Morgan and Rutherford (1998, pp. 21–
5) have reminded us, “pluralism” is a more accurate description of the state of play
in economics between the two world wars, reflecting the considerable variety
that actually prevailed in modes of investigation, techniques of analysis, and
types of policy advice. The extraordinary uniformity in the global analytic style
of the economics profession that we nowadays characterize as neoclassical eco-
nomics only dates from the 1950. The term “neoclassical economics” as a stand-
ard label for the mainstream of modern economics over the past century, going
back as far as the Marginal Revolution of the 1870s, is confusing enough because
the early pioneers of marginalism saw themselves as post-classicals, rejecting the
classical economics of Smith, Ricardo, and Mill, and would have decisively re-
jected the label “neoclassical” that was invented by Veblen in 1900 (Aspromourgos,
1986). But to apply the same label to prewar and postwar orthodox economics is
396 M. BLAUG
doubly confusing because, faced with such leading monographs of the 1940s and
1950s as, say, Samuelson’s Foundations of Economic Analysis (1947) and Arrow’s


Social Choice and Individual Values (1951), and with Arrow and Debreu’s “Exist-
ence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy” (1954), no prewar orthodox
economist could have made head or tail of them.
In short, economics underwent a metamorphosis in the late 1940s and 1950s
whatever one calls it. I call it a Formalist Revolution, after Ward, because it was
marked by extreme “formalism” – not just a preference, but an absolute prefer-
ence for the form of an economic argument over its content – which frequently
(but not necessarily) implies reliance on mathematical modeling and whose
ultimate objective is, like the notorious Hilbert program in mathematics, the
complete axiomatization of economic theory. It is perfectly possible to employ
mathematics elegantly (like Cournot in 1938) or clumsily (like Walras in 1871)
and yet eschew formalism in the sense that the mathematics is employed not for
its own sake but in order to throw more light on certain aspects of economic
reality. It is also possible not to employ mathematics at all (like Joan Robinson in
1956) and yet be highly formalistic in that the logic of the analysis is emphasized
irrespective of whether it serves to illuminate economic phenomena. Economists
emerged from World War II covered in glory because their technical expertise
proved surprisingly useful in dealing with military problems, employing such
new optimizing techniques as linear programming and activity analysis (Mirowski,
1998; Goodwin, 1998). In all of these exercises, mathematics figured heavily and
yet the Formalist Revolution was much more than the application of mathemat-
ical techniques to economics. It was, rather, reveling in mathematical modeling
as an end in itself and treating the equilibrium solution of the economic model as
the final answer to the question that prompted the investigation in the first place.
The Formalist Revolution made the existence and determinacy of equilibrium
the be-all and end-all of economic analysis. But what is new in that? Surely,
pinning down the equilibrium solution of a model had always been the aim of
economic theory? Well, yes and no. Equilibrium is the end-state of a process that
we economists think of as competition, but economic analysis can emphasize
the nature of the end-state or the nature of the competitive process that may

converge on an end-state – but it can rarely do both in equal measure. What is
little understood about the Formalist Revolution of the 1950s is precisely that
the process-conception of equilibrium was so effectively buried in that period
that what is now called neoclassical orthodox, mainstream economics consists
entirely of end-state equilibrium theorizing, with process-analysis relegated
entirely to unorthodox Austrian economics or equally unorthodox evolutionary
economics. Let me explain.
25.2 THE ARROW–DEBREU RESTATEMENT OF WALRAS
The centerpiece of my story is the famous 1954 paper by Arrow and Debreu, not
just because it is regarded to this day as a truly rigorous proof of the existence
of general equilibrium in a market economy, the fulfillment of Walras’s dream
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 397
80 years earlier, but because it is the perfect example of how concentration on
the precise nature of equilibrium can crowd out disequilibrium analysis. As soon
as it appeared it was hailed for its bold use of new mathematical techniques,
replacing differential calculus by convex analysis, characterizing equilibria by
separation theorems instead of tangencies, and employing the then relatively
new tools of game theory and Nash equilibria (Weintraub, 1991, pp. 104–7). What
was little noticed at the time was that this was also one of the earliest dramatic
uses in economics of the so-called “indirect proof method” of modern mathem-
atics. Arrow and Debreu used Brouwer’s “fixed-point theorem” to prove the
existence of general equilibrium, and the essence of the fixed-point logic is to
demonstrate a conclusion by showing that its violation involves an inconsistency
by contradicting one or more axioms of the model. Such a “nonconstructive”
proof jumps directly from the axioms of the model to its final outcome: instead of
constructing an example of whatever it is that is being justified, in this case
existence of equilibrium, it argues instead that equilibrium is logically implied by
one or more of the axioms. Modern existence proofs à la Arrow and Debreu are
nonconstructive in that they make no effort to show how equilibrium comes
about, but merely that it is reasonable to conceive of the existence of equilibrium.

One might say that they are possibility-of-existence proofs, not actual existence
proofs.
Furthermore, Arrow and Debreu are perfectly frank in disavowing any claims
that general equilibrium theory provides a descriptively accurate picture of the
economy. By the end, they are compelled to assume the existence of forward
markets for all goods and services traded, the absence of idle money balances
held by economic agents, the absence of market-makers holding inventories, the
absence of bank credit, and so on, in order to prove the existence of multi-market
equilibrium, and even so they find that they can throw no light on the unique-
ness or stability of general equilibrium.

As they concede (Arrow and Debreu,
1954, p. 266): “The latter study [of stability] would require specification of the
dynamics of a competitive market as well as the definition of equilibrium.” No
wonder, then, that they made use of Nash’s relatively new concept of equilib-
rium to solve the game of “an abstract economy,” because the justification for a
Nash equilibrium is a negative one: a Nash equilibrium in a noncooperative
game is such that each rational player’s strategy maximizes his or her expected
payoff against the given strategy of the other rational players; nothing other than
a Nash equilibrium can be the solution of such a game. Note that this says
nothing about the process whereby the equilibrium is obtained; it is absolutely
silent about the expectations of the players, the revision of plans, their epistemic
learning capacities, and so forth; equilibrium is simply imposed as a fixed point
in which market adjustments have come to an end (Weintraub, 1991, p. 108).
It is not difficult to see that the Arrow–Debreu article is formalism run riot,
in the sense that what was once an economic problem – Is simultaneous multi-
market equilibrium actually possible? – has been transformed into a mathematical
problem, which is solved, not by the standards of the economics profession, but
by those of the mathematics profession. This is Bourbakism pure and simple,
named after a changing group of French mathematicians who, since 1939, have

398 M. BLAUG
been producing an encyclopedic work on mathematical structures that exempli-
fies the Hilbertian axiomatic method. Debreu was a self-declared Bourbakian
and produced his own Theory of Value (1959), which carried the formalism of the
Arrow–Debreu paper one step further: “Allegiance of rigor dictates the axiomatic
form of the analysis where the theory, in its strict sense, is logically entirely
disconnected from its interpretation” (Debreu, 1959, p. 3).
25.3 THE RISE AND FALL OF GAME THEORY
One of the historical puzzles that lies directly across our central decade of the
1950s is the virtual disappearance of game theory in the 1950s and 1960s after
bursting on the scene in 1944 with the publication of The Theory of Games and
Economic Behavior by von Neumann and Morgenstern. There is little doubt about
the widespread disillusion among economists with early game theory, probably
because it offered definite solutions only for two-person, constant-sum games,
which are largely irrelevant for economics (Luce and Raiffa, 1957, pp. 10–11;
Dorfman, Samuelson, and Solow, 1958, p. 445). After virtually passing into
oblivion in the 1970s, game theory made an astonishing comeback in the 1980s;
by 1985 game theory in general, and Nash equilibrium in particular, became just
about the only language in economics with which to analyze the interactive
behavior of rational agents. When we consider that game theory is perhaps the
only example of a mathematical theory explicitly invented for the social sciences,
its steady decline for something like a generation is almost as mysterious as its
enthusiastic revival in the past two decades.
Giocoli (2000a,b) seems to me to provide a convincing explanation of the fall
and rise of game theory in economics, which ties together a number of elements
in our own story; namely, the disappearance of disequilibrium analysis, the
increasing concentration on the end-state of equilibrium, and the sinister ap-
pearance of fixed-point logic in the treatment of equilibrium. Both interwar
microeconomics and business cycle theory focused its analysis on what Giocoli
calls the “how and why” of equilibrium. Equilibrium had long been represented

in economics as a balance of forces, but it was Hayek in a number of essays in the
1930s who broke with this standard mechanical conception of equilibrium by
introducing the essentially dynamic concept of equilibrium as a situation in which
all the plans of agents are reconciled and made mutually consistent, such as to
confirm their plans and expectations (Ingrao and Israel, 1990, ch. 8; Weintraub,
1991, chs. 2, 5). In short, what emerged as the central question in prewar economics
was just how self-interested agents in a multi-period decision-making context
learn to formulate and revise their plans. However, early game theory as summed
up in von Neumann and Morgenstern’s opus did not derive from these concerns
in prewar orthodox economics, but from the mathematical formalism descended
from Hilbert. The average economist in the 1950s and 1960s, despite Arrow and
Debreu, could not quite grasp an equilibrium concept based on the formal logic
of fixed-point proofs, lacking any positive interpretation in a process that was
converging to equilibrium – and that is what accounts for the delayed acceptance
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 399
of early game theory by the economic community. The delayed acceptance
included the now ubiquitous Nash equilibrium concept because, as published in
1951, Nash’s papers defended the idea of Nash equilibrium by a negative, fixed-
point justification. In his doctoral dissertation, Nash (1996, pp. 32–3) offered a
positive justification for his equilibrium concept in what he called “mass action,”
or what we now call an “evolutionary” interpretation (Milath, 1998): in an iterative
adjustment process, boundedly rational players gradually learn to adjust their
own strategies to get a higher payoff after observing other players, a process that
eventually converges to a Nash equilibrium. However, Nash cut out the pages
proposing this from the published version of the thesis in the 1951 Annals of
Mathematics. Instead, he used the von Neumann–Morgenstern argument that if
each player had perfect knowledge of the game structure and perfect rationality
in the sense of instant computational powers, then equilibrium in a game would
necessarily be a set of payoffs, whose violation would be inconsistent with rational-
ity. This is precisely what we earlier called a negative justification for equilibrium.

All the old criticisms that had been constantly hurled at classical duopoly theory
– Why should duopolists continue myopically to assume constant reactions from
their rivals irrespective of experience? – were swept away by Nash’s invitation to
leap directly to the final long-run equilibrium without regard to any process of
adjustments converging on equilibrium. As Ken Binmore (Nash, 1996, p. xii)
rightly observed: “Nash’s 1951 paper allowed economists, not only to appreciate
the immensely wide range of possible applications of the idea of a Nash equilib-
rium, it also freed them of the need they had previously perceived to tie down
the dynamics of the relevant equilibrating process before being able to talk about
the equilibrium to which it will converge in the long run.”
When Arrow and Debreu employed game theory and the Nash equilibrium to
prove the existence of general equilibrium in the 1950s, the Formalist Revolution
was still in its early stages. It took another decade or more for formalism and
Bourbakianism to break down all resistance to game theory and fixed-point proofs
of noncooperative equilibria. It was only in the 1970s that Nash equilibrium was
accepted as the basic equilibrium concept of neoclassical economics, when it
was suddenly characterized as the very embodiment of the criterion of rationality
that, it was now claimed, had always been an essential feature of economic
theory.
25.4 BACK TO WALRAS
We have described the Arrow and Debreu paper as the capstone of the Walrasian
program, but we must now try to appraise their achievement from the vantage
point of a half-century later. The ascendancy of the end-state conception of
equilibrium and the almost total disappearance of the process-conception of
equilibrium, which is my language for what Arrow and Debreu managed to
accomplish, has its roots in Walras himself who, in successive editions of his
Elements of Pure Economics, allowed the existence-of-equilibrium question to drown
the problems of uniqueness and stability of equilibrium.
400 M. BLAUG
Walras’s original intention was to do much more than to demonstrate the

existence, uniqueness and stability of general equilibrium: it was also to provide
an abstract but nevertheless realistic study of the interdependence of markets in
a capitalist economy, and he never completely lost sight of that aim through four
editions of his Elements over a period of 26 years. Nevertheless, he fundamentally
altered his Elements between the third (1896) and fourth (1900) edition, intro-
ducing a new tâtonnement process for the model of capital formation and the
circulation of money. He had always eliminated disequilibrium transactions in
his model of pure exchange, misleadingly labeling them as “false trading”; in the
fourth edition he also eliminated disequilibrium production decisions, introduc-
ing the fiction that the transactors communicated, not orally or by the physical
signals implied by the appearance of out-of-equilibrium production quantities,
but by written pledges of their intentions to purchase or sell at various prices
“cried randomly.” Walras never explained why he made these changes but,
apparently, he thought that genuinely to allow disequilibrium transactions
threatened the cogency of the demonstration that there were always enough inde-
pendent equations to solve for the unknown prices and quantities, which was
his version of a proof of the existence of general equilibrium (Walker, 1996;
Bridel, 1997, ch. 4; Costa, 1998, ch. 2; De Vroey, 1999). He never made any effort to
prove “uniqueness” of the price vector that secures general equilibrium and in
respect of either local or global stability of equilibrium, he seems to have blandly
assumed that the tâtonnement process of price adjustments as a positive function
of the excess demand for commodities is always proportional to the amount of
excess demand, in which case equilibrium would indeed be stable whatever the
length of the stabilizing process.
The fate of Walras’s Elements is not unlike that of von Neumann and
Morgenstern’s Theory of Games and Economic Behavior: it suffered a gradual de-
mise after Walras’s death in 1910 and by, say, 1930 it is doubtful that there were
more than a half-dozen economists in the world who had ever read Walras,
much less understood him. From this state of total neglect began the rise, which
eventually brought GE (general equilibrium) theory to the front ranks of economic

theory in the postwar years. It was Hicks, Hotelling, Lange, and Samuelson
who were responsible in the golden decade of the 1930s in bringing about this
remarkable revival of GE theory (Blaug, 1997a, pp. 77–8; Samuelson, 1989,
p. 1384n). In the writings of these earlier defenders of Walras, GE theory was
treated as a quasi-realistic description of a market economy, which was perfectly
capable of confronting practical questions, such as the feasibility of “market
socialism.” But in the work of contemporary Viennese mathematicians, such as
Karl Schlesinger, Abraham Wald, and John von Neumann, GE theory began to
undergo axiomatization, setting aside all concerns with verisimilitude, let alone
empirical verification, leading directly to the Arrow–Debreu paper and Debreu’s
Theory of Value in which GE theory is boldly defended as a self-sufficient
mathematical structure, having no necessary contact with reality, or at most, as
in Arrow and Hahn’s General Competitive Analysis (1971), representing a purely
formal picture of the determination of economic equilibrium in an idealized
decentralized competitive economy. Considering that this metamorphosis took
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 401
less than a generation, this is really one of the remarkable Gestalt-switches in the
interpretation of a major economic theory in the entire history of economic thought.
25.5 IS GE THEORY MORIBUND?
Let us briefly consider how the neo-Walrasian research program has turned out
some 50 years after Arrow and Debreu. The existence proof of Arrow and Debreu
stands up today as it did in 1954, if only because the method of indirect proof
that they employed is logically impeccable and is immune to revision on grounds
of new evidence, being concerned with little else than the notional consistency of
the trading plans of purely virtual agents. What it signifies, however, is another
question. It is difficult to see how or why such negative proofs should ever have
been thought to be of economic interest inasmuch as the method of proof bears
no resemblance to any recognizable economic mechanism. Even if we suppose
that disequilibrium prices are ruled out by assumption, the interesting question
of how trading plans based on predetermined equilibrium prices can actually be

carried out is never even raised. Indeed, the very idea of demonstrating a link
between the mathematical solution of the existence problem and the outcome
of market interaction was simply abandoned by Arrow and Debreu. In short,
what is missing in GE theory and hence in Neowalrasian microeconomics is,
quite simply, competitive rivalry between transactors in actual markets. We have
forgotten that, as Clower (1994, p. 806) aptly put it, “the invisible hand also has
‘fingers’” (see Costa, 1998, ch. 4).
So much, then, for the existence problem. As for uniqueness, it has been shown
that general equilibrium entails one and only one price vector if and only if all
commodities are gross substitutes for one another, an assumption that is, to
put it mildly, highly unlikely to be true. Finally, there is the crucial question of
stability. The static properties of equilibrium have no practical meaning, unless
they persist in the face of small disturbances and emerge fairly quickly after
the appearance of disturbances. To believe in GE theory is to rely on the dynamic
stability of equilibrium (Fisher, 1983, p. 2). Now it is perfectly true that the
hypothesis of relative stability possesses an inherent plausibility because as
Samuelson (1947, p. 5) once said, “How many times has the reader seen an
egg standing on its end?” But that is probably due to the presence of nonprice
coordinating mechanisms, such as particular conventions and institutions,
market rules and procedures, technological constraints, and the like, all of which
do little to establish the stabilizing properties of GE pricing models. Despite a
considerable literature on local and global stability, the upshot of the discussion
so far is a more or less total impasse: not only are we unable to prove that
competitive markets are invariably stable but we have gained little insight as to
the features of markets that render them more or less stable (Ingrao and Israel,
1990, pp. 361–2).
We reach the curious conclusion that equilibrium in GE theory is known not to
be either unique or stable, and that its very existence can only be demonstrated
indirectly by a negative proof. Nevertheless, GE theory continues to be regarded
402 M. BLAUG

as the fundamental framework for theoretical discourse and the basis of comput-
able macroeconomic models. It is even taken to be the essential basis of project
evaluations in welfare economics. Is this yet another example of an emperor who
has no clothes (Kirman, 1989)?
25.6 RESPONSES TO THE FAILURE OF GE THEORY
There have been a number of responses to the apparent failure of GE theory to
live up to its own promises: to deliver rigorous solutions to the problems of the
existence, uniqueness, and stability of equilibrium. One response is to claim that
GE theory, despite its limitations, can somehow be employed negatively to refute
certain widely held economic propositions. That was Frank Hahn’s classic defense
and I have elsewhere argued against this ju-jitsu move (Blaug, 1990, ch. 8).
Another response is simply to hedge ones bets in the hope that any moment
now GE theory will suddenly be transformed by a dose of realism. Ingrao and
Israel’s path-breaking study of the history of GE theory seems to take this route:
it actually praises Debreu for exposing the logical errors of the theory, complains
of the character of GE theory in its Arrow–Debreu version, and then expresses
the hope that the relations between theory and empirical reality will soon be
“re-examined” (Ingrao and Israel, 1990, p. 362).
More interesting than any of these is Weintraub’s defense by way of
“constructivism.” For Weintraub (1991, pp. 108–9), “equilibrium is a feature of
our models, not the world” and stability of equilibrium is not something “out
there” in the economy. His study of the stability literature is “constructivist”:
knowledge in science, as well as knowledge about the history of science, is
socially constructed in the sense that it has meaning only within the discourse
of the relevant community, in this case that of economists. So, questions about
scientific validity, or empirical support for GE theory, have no meaning if only
because the theorists who played the Wittgenstein language game called GE
theory did not concern themselves with such questions. The book is studiously,
almost painfully, constructivist in never endorsing or criticizing the epistemic
claims of GE theory.

Weintraub is not always very clear as to the import of constructivism. Of
course, economic theories are constructed; of course, meanings are stabilized by
the language games that economists play. “Models and theorems and evidence
of various nature, empirical and formal and definitional,” he notes (ibid., p. 127),
“are adduced to convince other members of the concerned community that some
meanings are preferable for the agreed purposes.” Why is this truism worth
saying? Surely, what we want to know as historians of economic thought is why
some “evidence of various nature” and “some meanings” are regarded as more
persuasive than others. Are we really to believe that the claim that queues at
grocery stores are ipso facto proof of disequilibrium in food retail markets, or that
an economy with massive unemployment is not in macroeconomic equilibrium,
are just assertions about the logical properties of models and say nothing about
the state of the world? Whatever happened to the “correspondence rules” that all
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 403
of us attach to economic theories, explicitly or implicitly? When economists are
told that a tax on butter will raise the equilibrium price of butter, they have
learned from the “correspondence rules” of the theory of market equilibrium that
to test this conjecture they will need to study the price elasticities of the demand
for and supply of butter. They will regard the proposition in question as having
considerable relevance for policy, because it involves definite assertion about the
nature of reality and not just moves in a language game.
Notice how different is this defense of equilibrium from the one offered by
Frank Hahn in 1973. The standard view of equilibrium was, according to Hahn
(1973), to consider it as the outcome of a process, in which case it was useful only
if economic processes could be shown to actually converge on equilibrium. Alter-
natively, it is useful because it is a set of simultaneous and mutually compatible
plans in which all learning has ceased: it makes precise the limits of economic
analysis since he claimed that we have no theory of learning. We can only specify
a final equilibrium state because no rigorous general theory of disequilibrium
is possible. So, an end-state conception of equilibrium is needed because we

have no adequate process-conception that will tell us how actual expectations
and plan revisions converge to the end-state (but see Weibull, 1995; Fudenberg and
Levine, 1998). Now, Hahn’s argument is unduly influenced by his mathematical
notion of what constitutes an adequate rigorous theory, but he at any rate seems
to believe that an end-state equilibrium is somehow “out there” and that it can be
found in real time with the aid of certain “correspondence rules.”
Weintraub’s “constructivist” interpretation of equilibrium is the last stage in
his long journey over several books and many years to an impregnable defense
of GE theory. If general equilibrium is not an actual real state of affairs that could
conceivably happen, but just a heuristic device, a point of reference, a way of
talking, then to ask whether there are missing markets for some goods or whether
agents have perfect foresight has the same sort of meaning as to ask whether
there really are an infinite number of primes or whether the square root of a
negative number does require the imaginary number i. If Weintraub is right, we
need to reconstruct the entire subject of economics, because economists have
apparently deceived themselves about economic theory for over four centuries.
25.7 PERFECT COMPETITION AND ALL THAT
There is one element in the story that we have so far ignored, but we must now
bring it in to round off the argument about the shortcomings of GE theory. It is
the concept of perfect competition, which, surprisingly enough, was invented
de novo by Cournot in 1838 (Machovec, 1995, ch. 2; Blaug, 1997a, pp. 67–71). The
concept itself and the analytic habits of thought associated with it, particularly
the concentration on an end-state conception of competitive equilibrium in
which firms appear solely as passive price-takers, was alien not just to the great
economists of the classical past but even to the early marginalists in the last
quarter of the nineteenth century (with the sole exception of Edgeworth). The
perfectly competitive model which we now think of as standard neoclassical
404 M. BLAUG
microeconomics made its debut in the writings of Frank Knight in the 1920s and
then hardened into dogma by the spread of imperfect and monopolistic competi-

tion theory in the 1930s (Machovec, 1995, ch. 8; Blaug, 1997a, p. 68).
It involved the suppression of the idea that markets might adjust, not in terms
of price but in terms of quantity, or at least more quickly in terms of quantity
than in terms of price. Marshall and Walras never saw eye to eye in respect of the
stability conditions of a competitive market, but neither made it clear that the
disagreement was a disagreement about the concrete process of competition
(Blaug, 1997, pp. 72–6). In Marshall it is the production economy in which sellers
adjust output in response to excess demand price that is the paradigmatic case
of market adjustment, whereas in Walras it is the exchange economy in which
buyers adjust price offers in response to excess demand that is taken to be the
typical case. The revival of GE theory in the 1930s buried the very idea of quan-
tity adjustments even in labor markets, and once the Formalist Revolution got
under way in the 1950s, the virtual ban on disequilibrium analysis completed the
triumph of price adjustments as the only way that markets ever respond to
shocks. In a brand of economics that was increasingly static, all the nonprice
forms of competition – favorable locations, product innovations, advertising wars,
quicker deliveries, improved maintenance and service guarantees, and so on –
were assigned to such low-prestige subjects as marketing and business studies.
Even industrial organization, the one sub-field in economics in which students
of business behavior might expect to learn something about competitive rivalry,
only survived as part of the standard curriculum offering of a university eco-
nomics department in the 1970s and 1980s by adapting game theory as its principal
analytic tool.
Perfect competition never existed, nor ever could exist, as all the textbooks
agree (Blaug, 1997a, pp. 70–1), and yet the real world is said to be approximately
like, not far from, or even very close to the idealized world of perfect com-
petition. How do we know? Because historical comparisons tell us so and it is
such informal, nonrigorous appraisals that convince us that competitive mar-
kets perform better than centrally planned economies. Market economies are
informationally parsimonious, technically dynamic, and responsive to consumer

demand, and that is why we rate capitalism over socialism despite periodic
business depressions and unequal income distributions (Nelson, 1981). In short,
we appraise the private enterprise system in terms of the consequences of market
processes and leave all the beautiful statical properties of end-state equilibria to
classroom examination questions.
25.8 A CONFIRMATION AND A COUNTER-EXAMPLE
Let us now come back to the 1950s. Almost in the same month that Arrow and
Debreu published their seminal paper on the existence of general equilibrium,
Joan Robinson (1953–4) precipitated the Cambridge–Cambridge debate in
capital theory, at least when it was followed a decade later by Samuelson’s
surrogate production function article in 1962, the Quarterly Journal of Economics
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 405
symposium on capital-reversing and capital-reswitching in 1962 and, finally, the
Harcourt (1969) survey article in the Journal of Economic Literature in 1969. From
the beginning, this debate was not about the workings of the economy, but about
the logical properties of economic models: Is there a strictly monotonic relation-
ship between a change in the rate of interest and the capital–labor ratio, and is
the rate of interest a function of the relative scarcity of capital in the economy
as alleged in the neoclassical theory of distribution? Now, one might have
thought that the issue is essentially an empirical one – How likely is it for the
reswitching of interest rates to occur? – but with few exceptions both parties in
the debate insisted vehemently that a logical flaw in a comprehensive economic
theory can never be repaired by empirical evidence (Blaug, 1990, ch. 10). This
is not the place to adjudicate this famous dispute, but what is striking about
this 20-year-long debate is its entirely formalistic character. No one, whether
on one side of the Atlantic or the other, ever asked: What do we learn about
the economy if we decide that reswitching does or does not occur, and what
follows about economic policy?
Notice too the extraordinary resemblance of this discussion about capital theory
to the Arrow–Debreu existence proof: once Cambridge US capitulated and agreed

that reswitching is logically possible, the debate dried up, as if the uses of an
essentially static equilibrium framework to address issues of dynamic processes
had been fully exhausted. In a striking essay on the nature of economic science,
Donald McCloskey (1991) wrote: “From everywhere outside of economics except
the department of Mathematics the proof of the existence of competitive
equilibrium . . . will seem strange. They do not claim to show that an actual exist-
ing economy is in equilibrium, or that the equilibrium of an existence economy
is desirable. They show that certain equations describing a certain blackboard
economy have a solution, but they do not give the solution to the blackboard
problem, much less to an extant economy.” The analogy with the reswitching
debate is perfect: reswitching cannot logically be excluded from the neoclassical
marginal productivity theory of distribution. So what?
That brings us to the one undisputed example of formalism in the 1950s: growth
theory of the Solow–Swann variety that appeared full-blown in 1956 (Hacche,
1979). This was no “inquiry into the causes of the wealth of nations” but a study
of the necessary features of steady-state growth – that is, equiproportionate
increases in all the relevant economic variables of economic models into the
indefinite future – whose ability to shed light on actual economies growing in
real historical time was called into question by even its leading practitioners.
Modern growth theory, John Hicks (1965, p. 183) admitted, “has been fertile in
the generation of classroom exercises: and so far as we can yet see, they are exer-
cises, not real problems. They are not even hypothetical real problems, of the type
‘what would happen if?’ where ‘if’ is something that could conceivably happen.
They are shadows of real problems dressed up in such a way that by pure logic
we can find solutions for them.” Does this conclusion remind us of anything?
The next example is much more controversial: The Production of Commodities by
Means of Commodities by Piero Sraffa, published in 1960 at the very close of the
decade with which we have been concerned. The book begins with an economy
406 M. BLAUG
in an end-state of long-run equilibrium and the author wastes no words telling

us how we have got there, or what would happen if we departed from it: homo-
geneous labor is the only nonreproducible input, whose amount is given at the
outset of the analysis; fixed input-coefficients prevail in all industries (firms are
never mentioned) and, hence, production would obey constant returns to scale
if output ever varied, a possibility that is explicitly ruled out; the profit rate is
equalized between industries, from which we infer that producers maximize
profits and minimize unit costs, but not a word is spent considering the motivation
of individuals; and the economy is closed and the pattern of demand obviously
plays no role in determining prices, although it must equally obviously affect the
scales of output of each industry.
The mode of exposition of the book is entirely Walrasian, and by page 5 we are
already counting equations and unknowns to see if they match as a means of
ensuring ourselves that we have a determinate solution for prices and quantities.
It turns out that to determine both relative prices and the rate of profit, we must
take the rate of wages as given, a conclusion that is central to Sraffa’s basic thesis
that the theory of value or the determination of prices is divorced from the
determination of income distribution, the latter depending essentially on a power
struggle between capital and labor. Whether this is in fact the central conclusion
of the book is itself controversial. The book is tightly argued and abounds in
beautiful logical puzzles – the definition of “the standard system,” the definition
of “joint production,” the distinction between basics and nonbasics, and so forth
– and even now, 42 years later, the purpose of Sraffa’s book is so opaquely
expressed that commentators cannot agree on what it adds up to (Moseley, 1995,
ch. 1); this may well be one of its central attractions. Its sub-title was “A prelude
to a critique of economic theory,” but this apparent aim of undermining neoclas-
sical economics and recovering the classical political economy of Ricardo and
Marx only confuses the issue of its aims still further, because classical economics
was a theory of a moving equilibrium or, rather, a moving demand disequilibrium,
since neither the labor market nor the capital market was imagined to be in the
state of long-run equilibrium, which of course is why the rate of population

growth and the rate of capital accumulation was assumed to be positive (Blaug,
1999).
Again, this is not the occasion to attempt to unravel the real meaning of Sraffa’s
gnostic text, but simply to underline its total commitment to formalism. The real
world is referred to once in the whole book, and for the rest we are totally
immersed in a logical world of Sraffa’s own making, whose very connection with
a previous intellectual tradition is problematic. It is no wonder that despite a
considerable following, at least in Europe, the Sraffian Research Program has
produced little more than analytic refinement of the original model and not a
single substantial insight into any concrete economic problem (see Steedman’s
entirely negative defense in Moseley, 1995, pp. 18–19). If ever economics was
guilty of being a language game rather like Scholastic philosophy, Sraffian eco-
nomics is an almost perfect corroboration of the thesis.
I bring the argument to a close with a counter-example: the one clear example
where adherence to the framework of GE theory brought an incontrovertible
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 407
benefit: I refer to Don Patinkin’s Money, Interest and Prices (1956). This book,
which should have brought Patinkin the Nobel Prize twice over, not only inte-
grated money and value theory, developed the notion of the real balance effect
and recovered its pivotal role in the classical quantity theory of money, and
unified GE theory with the Keynesian concept of “unemployment equilibrium,”
but made a number of pioneering contributions to the history of economic thought
with a series of “Supplementary Notes” that were scandalously omitted from the
second abridged edition, published in 1989. I have returned expectedly in the
above to the steady omission of disequilibrium analysis, but that is one accusa-
tion of which Patinkin is innocent. The book is perhaps best known for its inter-
pretation of Keynesian economics as a theory of unemployment, dealing not with
a situation of static underemployment equilibrium, but with one of dynamic
disequilibrium, in which markets adjust too slowly to bring about full unem-
ployment in the time-span under consideration. The “neoclassical synthesis”

was a label coined by Samuelson in the fifth edition of his Economics (1955),
but Weintraub (1991, pp. 123–4) is quite right to hail Patinkin as the one who
truly “created the neoclassical synthesis as we understand it.” Even in his exegesis
of nineteenth- and twentieth-century monetary theorists, Patinkin did more
than anyone else to remind us that the nonneutrality of money in short-run dis-
equilibrium was just as much part of the quantity theory of money as the much
vaunted long-run neutrality of money, and perhaps even more so (Blaug,
1997b, pp. 615–16). Patinkin demonstrates that GE theory is not impelled by its
logical structure totally to suppress the process of conception of equilibrium; it is
simply a mixture that does not easily blend. It is true, however, that Patinkin
carried the maddening tendency of Walrasians to settle real economic questions
by counting equations and unknowns to its breaking point. His famous assault
on the classical and neoclassical “dichotomization of the pricing process,” by
which relative prices are first determined in commodity markets and absolute
prices are then determined subsequently in the money market, rested on Walras’s
Law that there cannot be an excess demand for goods without an excess supply
for money. This wins an argument about the role of money in economic affairs
by an algebraic demonstration without lifting the chalk off the blackboard. It
was exactly like Hicks’s (1939, pp. 160–2) habit of settling the great Keynesian deb-
ate between the liquidity preference and loanable funds theories of interest by
asking which equation to drop, the money equation or the goods equation. It is
precisely this rush to algebra so endemic in GE theory that dooms it to sterility.
25.9 CONCLUSION
The central question of orthodox prewar microtheory – How is market equilib-
rium actually attained? – has been shunted aside ever since the Formalist Revolu-
tion of the 1950s. In GE theory, the question of whether it is attained at all
dominated the issue of convergence to equilibrium so successfully as to swallow
it up entirely. Even game theory begged the question, because its definition of
equilibrium as the solution of a game makes sense once we have arrived at the
408 M. BLAUG

solution but in no way explains how we got there. That everything depends on
everything else is no reason to think that it depends on everything else simul-
taneously and instantly, without the passage of real time, that neither prices or
quantities are ever sticky, that since information is always symmetric for both
sides of the market there are no missing markets, or that price-taking is just as
universal out of equilibrium as in equilibrium – in short, that the metaphor of
thinking about price determination in terms of the mathematics of solving simul-
taneous equations has proved in the fullness of time to be grossly misleading.
With the triumph of formalism, the economists’ community began ever more
to resemble the community of mathematicians: finding an elegant generalization
of an established result, or a new application of a well-known concept, became
the only desiderata of young aspirants in the subject; cleverness, not wisdom or a
concern with actual economic problems, now came to be increasingly rewarded
in departments of economics around the world. The past half-century has only
seen a continuous onward march of this trend. The Formalist Revolution was a
watershed in the history of economic thought, and the economists of today are
recognizably the children of the revolutionaries of the 1950s.
Bibliography
Arrow, K. J. and Debreu, G. 1954: Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy.
Econometrica, 22(3), 265–90.
Aspromourgos, T. 1986: On the origins of the term “neoclassical.” Cambridge Journal of
Economics, 10, 265–70.
Blaug, M. 1990: The Methodology of Economics, 2nd edn. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
—— 1997a: Competition as an end-state and competition as a process. In Not Only an
Economist. Recent Essays. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 66–86.
—— 1997b: Economic Theory in Retrospect, 5th edn. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
—— 1999: Misunderstanding classical economics: the Sraffian interpretation of the surplus
approach. History of Political Economy, 31(2), 213–36.

Bridel, P. 1997: Money and General Equilibrium Theory. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Clower, R. C. 1994: Economics as an inductive science. Southern Economic Journal, 60(4),
805–14.
Costa, M. L. 1998: General Equilibrium: Analysis and the Theory of Markets. Cheltenham, UK:
Edward Elgar.
Debreu, G. 1959: Theory of Value. An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
De Vroey, M. 1999: Transforming Walras into a Marshallian economist: a critical review of
Donald Walker’s Walras’s Market Models. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 21(4),
413–36.
Dorfman, R., Samuelson, P. A., and Solow, R. M. 1958: Linear Programming and Economic
Analysis. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Fisher, F. M. 1983: Disequilibrium Foundations of Equilibrium Economics. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Fudenberg, F. and Levine, D. 1998: The Theory of Learning in Games. Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press.
THE FORMALIST REVOLUTION OF THE 1950S 409
Giocoli, G. 2000a: Fixing the point. The contribution of early game theory to the tool box
of modern economics. Unpublished paper, Department of Economics, University of
Pisa.
—— 2000b: Equilibrium and rationality in modern economics: from the years of “high
theory” to the foundation of modern game theory. Ph.D. thesis, Università degli Studi
di Firenze.
Goodwin, C. D. 1998: The patrons of economics in a time of transformation. In M. S.
Morgan and M. Rutherford (eds.), From Interwar Pluralism to Postwar Neoclassicism,
Annual Supplement to vol. 30 of History of Political Economy, 53–87.
Hacche, G. 1979: The Theory of Economic Growth. London: Macmillan.
Hahn, F. 1973: On the Notion of Equilibrium in Economics: An Inaugural Lecture. Cam-
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Hahn, F. 1984: Equilibrium and
Macroeconomics. Oxford: Blackwell, 43–71.

Harcourt, G. C. 1969: Some Cambridge controversies in the theory of capital. Journal of
Economic Literature, 7(2), 369–405.
Hicks, J. R. 1939: Value and Capital. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
—— 1965: Capital and Growth. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Ingrao, B. and Israel, G. 1990: The Invisible Hand: Economic Equilibrium in the History of
Science. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.
Kirman, A. 1989: The intrinsic limits of modern economic theory: the emperor has no
clothes. Economic Journal, 99, 126–39.
Luce, R. D. and Raiffa, H. 1957: Games and Decisions. New York: John Wiley.
Machovec, F. M. 1995: Perfect Competition and the Transformation of Economics. London:
Routledge.
McCloskey, D. N. 1991: Economic science: a search through the hyperspace of assump-
tions. Methodus, 3(1), 6–16. Reprinted in S. T. Ziliak (ed.) 2001: Measurement and Meaning
in Economics. The Essential Deirdre McCloskey, vol. 3. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar,
23–4.
Milath, G. J. 1998: Do people play Nash equilibrium? Lessons from evolutionary game
theory? Journal of Economic Literature, 3(3), 1347–74.
Mirowski, P. 1998: Machine dreams: economic agents as cyborgs. In J. B. Davis (ed.), New
Economics and Its History, Annual Supplement to vol. 29 of History of Political Economy,
13–40.
Morgan, M. S. and Rutherford, M. 1998: American economics: the character of the
transformation. In M. S. Morgan and M. Rutherford (eds.), From Interwar Pluralism to
Postwar Neoclassicism. Annual Supplement to vol. 30 of History of Political Economy,
1–26.
Moseley, F. 1995: Heterodox Economic Theories. True or False? Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar.
Nash, J. F. 1996: Essays in Game Theory. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Nelson, R. R. 1981: Assessing private enterprise: an exegesis of tangled doctrine. Bell
Journal of Economics, 2(1), 93–111. Reprinted in P. J. Boettke (ed.), The Legacy of Friedrich
von Hayek, vol. III. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 80–98.
Patinkin, D. 1956: Money, Interest and Prices: An Interpretation of Money and Value Theory.

Evanston, IL: Peterson; 2nd edn. Harper & Row, 1965; 2nd edn. abridged, Harper &
Row, 1989.
Robinson, J. 1953–4: The production function and the theory of capital. Review of Eco-
nomic Studies, 21, 81–106. Reprinted in Robinson, J. 1960: Collected Economic Papers,
vol. 2. Oxford: Blackwell, 114–31.
Samuelson, P. A. 1947: Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
410 M. BLAUG
—— 1989: How Foundations came to be. Journal of Economic Literature, 36(3), 1375–86.
Walker, D. A. 1996: Walras’s Market Models. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Ward, B. 1972: What’s Wrong with Economics? London: Macmillan.
Weibull, J. 1995: Evolutionary Game Theory, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Weintraub, E. R. 1991: Stabilizing Dynamics: Constructing Economic Knowledge. Cam-
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

×