Tải bản đầy đủ (.pdf) (18 trang)

Should vs ought to pdf ebook

Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (511.64 KB, 18 trang )

Should vs. Ought to

[Modals]

Should vs. Ought to*
Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

University College Ghent / Ghent University

0.  Preface
The seeds of this text were sown within Renaat Declerck’s ambitious
but unfinished project on mood and modality. At one project work meeting in 2006, one of us (B.C.) presented some quantitative findings about
significant factors in the choice between should and ought to, based on a
fairly restricted data set (150 examples of each modal verb). A mutual
comparison of the contributions of these factors was lacking, and this paper is an attempt to provide this. The idea of using an extensive set of
parameters to investigate the distribution of modal auxiliaries lay at the
heart of the modality project as formulated in its proposal. In this sense,
the present paper is in the spirit of Declerck’s research aims.

*  Many thanks go to Renaat Declerck for allowing the research within his final project, on mood and modality, to be conducted from different theoretical and descriptive
angles. This text, as well as the text by Ilse Depraetere in this volume, should prove
that such space for intellectual freedom can bear fruit which we hope will carry
Renaat’s approval. For the implicit views on modality, this text has undoubtedly benefited from the many e-mail exchanges and meetings with Ilse Depraetere, Susan Reed
and An Verhulst which took place within that project. We are also especially grateful
to Marie Baert and Fanny Lauwaers, who coded the corpus examples of should and
ought to in written discourse as part of their course work for the 2006-2007 master’s
course Descriptive English Linguistics: Selected Topics at K.U. Leuven. Finally, we
would like to thank Naoaki Wada for his helpful suggestions. Any remaining shortcomings are our own.

93


At the time, however, Declerck did not think that a multifactorial statistical analysis of the sort presented here would advance the project. 
Instead, he argued that larger sets of examples should instead be examined
with an eye to discovering rare or undescribed usage types. For this paper a set of examples more than three times the original size has been investigated, but our primary aim is not to report special types. Rather, our
intention is to show that systematic analysis and coding of what is still a
relatively restricted data set (approx. 500 authentic examples of each modal verb) can lead to confident conclusions about rarely described or hitherto undetected usage trends which distinguish these two semantically close
lexical items.

1.  Should and Ought to: The Challenge
As the following sentences demonstrate, should and ought (to) can be
used as what appear to be stylistic variants of each other (1a, b), as mutual
paraphrases to strengthen each other’s meaning (2a, b), and, most remarkably, in tag questions as proforms for verb phrases containing the other
verb, a possibility pointed out by Harris (1986: 353), Palmer (1990: 122),
Perkins (1983: 55) and Swan (1995: 496)—though note that, for reasons
that will become clear, a tag with shouldn’t is more frequent than one
with oughtn’t (3a, b):
(1) a.Tina had no moral sense about this question, no feeling that
children ought to know who their fathers were or should be
fathered by the men their mothers lived with or were married
to. (British National Corpus (henceforth BNC), written discourse)
b.Check the quality of the paper. It should not be limp, shiny
or waxy and the heavily printed areas ought to feel crisp and
slightly rough. (Cobuild corpus, Today Newspaper)
(2) a.I’m not all that I should be and all that I ought to be, but by
this time next year I’m going to be a bit better than I am just
now, in spiritual terms. (BNC, spoken discourse)

92

distinctions.indd 92-93


10.7.26 11:52:15 AM


94

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter



b.It is all very well setting goals—but what if the very idea
causes psychological reversals, or the athlete’s logical mind
says they ought, should, could do it while their emotional
mind says it doesn’t want to? (Cobuild corpus, UK books)
(3) a. Suppose I ought to tell him that shouldn’t I?
(BNC, spoken discourse)
b.And yes, we should be mindful of Muslims’ sensitivities. 
But such mindfulness really should run both ways, oughtn’t
it? ( />Such examples appear to confirm the received opinion about the modals
should and ought to, namely that they are so similar in meaning that they
can typically substitute for one another. For instance, Palmer (1990: 122)
writes, “It is not at all clear that (…) English makes any distinction between should and ought to. They seem to be largely interchangeable.” 
In Collins’s (2009: 52-53) summary of the literature, similar sentiments
are expressed by Coates (1983: 69), Quirk et al. (1985: 227) and
Huddleston and Pullum (2002: 186).
Both should and ought to can also be used as epistemic modals. 
Unlike in their deontic use, their function is then not to speak about obligations or to offer advice but rather to express that the fulfilment of a situation is quite likely or can be reasonably expected given some (perceived)
facts. For example:
(4) a.Michael Saunders, UK economist at Salomon Brothers, said
that with output prices already falling sharply, underlying inflation should drop below 2.5 per cent by the middle of this
year. (Cobuild corpus, The Times newspaper)

b.After all that, some morale-boosting planetary aspects on the
16th, 18th and 22nd ought to make you glow again.
(Cobuild corpus, UK magazines)
In their epistemic use, should and ought to convey a weaker version of
logical necessity as expressed by must. That means that they do not refer
to an inescapable conclusion. Indeed, sometimes they are even used

distinctions.indd 94-95

Should vs. Ought to

95

when the likelihood of a situation is zero (in counterfactual situations);
they then merely express that there was a reasonableness of expectation,
which the context makes clear is not borne out, as in the following examples:
(5) a.“You stupid fool,” he said aloud. “It should be obvious
what’s happening to the Lands. They’re dying.”

(Cobuild corpus, UK books)
b.“Why doesn’t the Thing know where to go?” said Gurder. 
“It could find Floridia, so somewhere important like
Blackbury ought to be no trouble.”
(BNC, written discourse)
Clearly, these examples show that should and ought to need not indicate
the speaker’s/writer’s supposition that the statement he makes is true. 
Quite often, an epistemic interpretation is mingled with a deontic one. 
Consider:
(6) a.Unless you are going somewhere subtropical, a wet suit is
essential, as is a “foamie”, a fat foam board specially designed for beginners. Any good surfing school should have

plenty of both. (Cobuild corpus, The Times newspaper)
b.Who’d like to tell me what twenty-six will be? And then the
next number? Jody. Come on nearly everybody ought to be
able to work this one out now. Eleanor. (…) That’s lovely. 
Can you all tell me together what twenty-eight will be?
(BNC, spoken discourse)
In (6a), there is both an epistemic sense (‘go to any good surfing school
and you’re likely to find that they have plenty of both’) and a deontic
sense (‘any good surfing school owes it to itself to have plenty of both’). 
Similarly, in (6b), the modal should in the teacher’s utterance is epistemic
(‘Since all these exercises are similar, I expect that this particular exercise
will not pose any difficulty’) but it is undeniably tinged with a deontic
reading (‘You’d better be able to work this one out, otherwise it’s clear to
me you haven’t paid any attention’). Note, crucially, that in these in-

10.7.26 11:52:15 AM


96

97

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Should vs. Ought to

stances of purely epistemic use or ‘merger,’ should and ought to are again
interchangeable.
Given the examples above and the generally accepted view that should
and ought to are semantically equivalent, the challenge is to establish on

which grounds, if any, should and ought to can nonetheless be distinguished.

2.1.  Subjectivity vs. Objectivity
Echoing Swan (1980: 550), Declerck (1991: 377, fn. 21) claims:
“Although should and ought to are often interchangeable, there is a slight
difference of meaning between them. When using should the speaker expresses his own subjective view; ought to is more objective and is used
when the speaker wants to represent something as a law, duty or regulation. For this reason ought to may sound more emphatic than should.”
Declerck offers the following contrast and accompanying comment, again
loosely based on Swan (1980: 550):

2.  Differences Proposed in the Literature
We are not the first to rise to the challenge of finding differences between should and ought to. Some linguists have been dissatisfied with
the generally acknowledged view that these modals are semantically
equivalent and have put forward claims about subtle semantic differences.
That there are differences in meaning between should and ought to is
only to be expected. Despite their different ancestry (should originally
being the past tense of shall and ought to the past tense of owe), the close
synonymy of should and ought to goes back to at least Old English (i.e.
to before the mid-twelfth century), as appears from attested examples
adopted in the Oxford English Dictionary (Simpson (2000)). The fact
that should and ought to have all this time been allowed to co-exist as
distinct forms occupying the same semantic patch “would seem to justify
the conclusion,” according to Visser (1963: 1637), “that they never had
exactly the same meaning, however closely synonymous they always have
been.”
Yet, exactly what distinguishes these two modals semantically is hard to
pin down. In the following subsections, we will consider three proposals
made in the literature: (i) subjectivity vs. objectivity, (ii) absence vs. presence of an implication of non-fulfilment and (iii) relative frequency vs. infrequency of epistemic reading.
In a final subsection, we will consider some other, non-semantic, differences proposed in the literature.


distinctions.indd 96-97

(7) a. You should / ought to congratulate her.
b.I ought to congratulate her, but I don’t think I will. (Should
would sound odd here: it would be strange to give yourself
advice and then add that you were not going to follow it.)
(Declerck (1991: 377, fn. 21))
Likewise, Collins (2009: 54) makes the claim (though without backing
it up with concrete figures) that while should and ought to are both “more
commonly subjective than objective (…) the proportion of objective cases
is higher with ought to.” He calls a deontic modal “subjective” when it
“indicates what the speaker considers desirable, appropriate or right”
(Collins (2009: 45)) or when “the speaker is giving advice authoritatively
to the addressee” (Collins (2009: 54)) and “objective” when “the appropriateness or desirability of the course of action described stands independ­
ently of the speaker’s endorsement” (Collins (2009: 45)), i.e., when “generally accepted standards of appropriate behaviour are being invoked”
(Collins (2009: 54)). A very similar distinction can be found in Myhill’s
(1996) study, who argues in detail that should expresses an individual
opinion while ought to stresses that an opinion is shared by a group. This
reference to shared opinion, associated with objectivity, can be further
linked to the claim that ought to, more strongly than should, suggests that
the obligation is a duty leading to the greater public good (cf. Gailor
(1983: 348); Aarts and Wekker (1987: 193)).
It is hard to test the impact of subjectivity objectively: in individual examples, it’s not always clear whether the source of modality is grounded

10.7.26 11:52:15 AM


98

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter


in the speaker/writer or in some speaker-external source. We have used a
somewhat different notion of subjectivity in our corpus investigation:
whenever the modality (whether grounded in the speaker/writer or in
some other source) emanates from a personal viewpoint, it is subjective;
when the modal statement is issued without the speaker taking a personal
stance whatsoever, it is objective.
One way of testing subjectivity indirectly but fairly reliably might be to
count the number of sentences in a corpus in which should and ought to
occur in a clause which is the complement of an expression of cognition
(assume, believe, feel, reckon, suppose, think, take the view, …). It can
be hypothesised that if should is relatively more subjective and ought to
relatively more objective, sentences like I think you should leave are more
frequent than I think you ought to leave.

2.2.  Absence vs. Presence of a Non-fulfilment Implication
Ought to has been claimed to suggest that the actualisation of the situation referred to “is overdue or may be delayed” (Close (1981: 121)) or
that it might not take place at all (Gailor (1983: 348-349)), implications
which are thought to be absent with should. As Westney (1995: 170) remarks, it could also be the reason why As you should know… is less aggressive than As you ought to know … as an opener to give (superfluous)
information or advice, since the latter would impolitely suggest that the
hearer might not yet know.
Support for Westney’s observation can be found in the relative normality of titles of websites or articles starting with “Ten things you ought to
know about…”: here the writer has a good motivation to assume or suggest that the reader does not yet have the knowledge about the relevant
topic, since otherwise writing the text would be rather pointless.
However, Westney correctly points out that the suggestion of non‌fulfilment is by no means always present with ought to, as is witnessed by
the following example:
(8)Whenever he got a chance, Malek broke into a canter, and one
of those bursts turned into a long twilight gallop; he may have

distinctions.indd 98-99


Should vs. Ought to

99

thought we were far from home and ought to get a move on…
(Leigh Fermer, Patrick (1986) Between the Woods and the
Water, Murray, London, quoted by Westney (1995: 168))
Non-fulfilment is therefore at best a (pragmatic) implicature rather than a
(semantic) implication (i.e. entailment) in the strict sense.
Sentences like (8), where actualisation of the situation can be deduced
from the context, are rather exceptional, however. Whether or not the situation actually comes to fulfilment is not coded in the modal but is usually something to be derived extra-linguistically. This neutrality with respect to actualisation especially holds when the proposition refers to a future situation (Palmer (1990: 123)).
In Degani’s (2009: 338) corpus-based study of ought to, the majority of
sentences are indeed “non-factual” (rather than “actualised” or “counterfactual”). In such sentences, ought to simply conveys the idea that there
is a situation whose actualisation is considered desirable or expected. It
is hard to verify via corpus research whether ought to in such cases, on
top of this notion of desirability or expectation, commonly suggests a
lesser likelihood of actualisation than if should had been used. In fact, it
would not be a reliable method to check whether the likelihood of fulfilment increases or decreases when replacing ought to by should in individual examples, since such judgments could only be made on a subjective
basis.
A more valid operationalisation would be to count the number of instances of should and ought to followed by a perfect infinitive (e.g. You
{should/ought to} have asked me first) or a present progressive (e.g. I
{should/ought to} be revising now), since these verb forms implicate
counterfactuality (but see section 5 for some complications).

2.3.  Relative Frequency vs. Infrequency of Epistemic Use
A number of linguists have claimed or reported that should conveys
epistemicity more commonly than ought to does. Coates (1983) reports
that the ratio of epistemic versus deontic uses is roughly 1:4 in the case of
should but only roughly 1:8 in the case of ought to. This difference is


10.7.26 11:52:16 AM


100

101

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Should vs. Ought to

even more pronounced in Collins’s (2009) recent corpus counts, from
which we can infer an epistemic/deontic ratio of about 1:6 for should and
of about 1:32 for ought to. According to Palmer (1987: 134), it is only
“theoretically possible to imagine ought to being used epistemically but
that seems very rarely to occur. In general ought to is interpreted deontically.” In Palmer (1990: 60) he even reports not to have found a single
example of epistemic ought to, although he acknowledges the existence of
cases of merger.
In sharp contrast, Degani’s (2009: 333) corpus counts of ought to in the
FLOB and Frown corpora (representing 1990s English in the UK and the
US, respectively) reveal percentages as high as 31% and 36% for the
epistemic use. Expressed as epistemic/deontic ratios (disregarding cases
of merger), this amounts to roughly 1:1.5 for UK English and almost 1:1
for US English. Interestingly, Degani also shows that the epistemic use
of ought to seems to have increased in frequency since the early 1960s,
from 21% in the LOB corpus (UK English) and 24% in the Brown corpus
(US English), or from epistemic/deontic ratios of roughly 1:3 and roughly
1:5, respectively.
We must conclude that the assessment of epistemic ought to differs

widely across studies, ranging from being only a theoretical possibility to
an interpretation which is as frequent as deontic ought to. Degani’s
(2009) study only reports recent changes in the use of ought to, so our
study will complement her study by comparing the use of ought to with
the use of should in 1990s UK English.

19:1.
Second, Celce-Murcia and Larsen-Freeman (1983: 89) claim that deontic should and deontic ought to contrast with each other in that the latter
is more informal (most markedly so if it is phonologically reduced to
oughta). Not differentiating between deontic and epistemic uses, a similar
register-based difference for ought to has been noted by Collins
(2009: 46): “Despite its small numbers in the present study, ought to was
found to be considerably more robust in British and American speech than
writing,” with the speech/writing ratios being roughly 3:1 and 4:1, respectively. (The number of epistemic uses of ought to was too low in
Collins’s study to allow a comparison between speech and writing.)
Collins (2009: 52) also notes that should is much more evenly distributed
across speech and writing, but that “deontic should shows a stronger tendency to be associated with the written word (…) than does epistemic
should.” This might be somewhat surprising, given that ought to has
been shown to be in serious decline (e.g. Leech (2003))—one usually expects to encounter archaic linguistic items in the written rather than the
spoken mode. But note that many remnants of older language phases
which have long disappeared from the standard language can be preserved
in dialects, which are by their nature also informal.
Finally, it has been stated that “unlike should, ought to occurs mostly in
positive statements, not in negative and interrogative sentences” (Harris
(1986), Aarts and Wekker (1987: 193)).

2.4.  Other Differences Proposed in the Literature
Apart from the semantic differences mentioned in the previous subsections, it has been noted that should and ought to differ in a number of
other respects.
First, and most conspicuously, should is much more frequent in use

than ought to. In the BNC, there are 111,237 occurrences of should but
only 5,979 occurrences of ought to (cf. Kennedy (2002)), which amounts
to a should/ought to ratio of 19:1. Similarly, in Collins’s (2009) study
(involving different corpora), the ratio of should to ought to appears to be

distinctions.indd 100-101

3.  The Present Study: Data, Parameters, Methodology
3.1.  Data
For both modals, should and ought to, we made sure that at least 500
occurrences in context were extracted from corpora of British English. 
Half of the occurrences are from the spoken part of the BNC, which was
searched with the accompanying SARA software. Oddly, the software did
not allow us to select all the written texts in the BNC in any obvious way,
which led to the decision to use another corpus, the Cobuild corpus, for
which we selected all the written subcorpora with British English lan-

10.7.26 11:52:16 AM


102

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

guage material. A difference between the BNC and the Cobuild Corpus
is that a search for should and ought in the BNC also yielded instances of
shouldn’t, shoulda, oughtn’t and oughta, whereas these forms had to be
looked up separately in Cobuild. We made sure that the number of examples of these forms extracted from Cobuild matched the proportion of the

number of base forms to the total occurrences in the corpus (about 1% for
should, about a third for ought). Table 1 provides an overview of the total number of hits for each search term and the number of hits actually
extracted. Obviously, all hits we extracted for our investigation were
chosen randomly.

Should
Shouldn’t
Shoulda
Ought
Oughtn’t
Oughta

Spoken (BNC)
Total Hits
Extracted
12113
250
(included in above)
(included in above)
  1278
250
(included in above)
(included in above)

Written (Cobuild corpus)
Total Hits
Extracted
25816
250
   896

   9
     7
   0
   719
250
    11
   4
     7
   2

Table 1: C
 orpus Finds and Number of Examples Extracted for All
Search Terms
It can be observed from the table that should is much more frequent than
ought to in the corpora, with a 9:1 should/ought to ratio in the spoken
corpus and a 36:1 should/ought to ratio in the written corpus. These frequencies confirm the general predominance of should and the relative informality of ought to mentioned in section 2.4.
Removed from the data were sentences which were severely anacoluthic
and non-interpretable, as well as sentences such as those in (9)-(13), containing should in a sense in which it simply could not be replaced by
ought to:
(9) a. I should like to ask Mick regarding the long service ambulance personnel. (BNC, spoken discourse)
b. I should say it’s convenient for neither I should imagine.

distinctions.indd 102-103

103

(BNC, spoken discourse)
c.When’s dad coming back?—I don’t know yet, I should think
it’ll be by the end of the month.  (BNC, spoken discourse)
d.I should sincerely hope not.

(Cobuild corpus, Times newspaper)
(10) a.Let me know if you need anything, or if someone close to
you should suddenly die. 
(Cobuild corpus, UK books)

b.Always try and make up a working prototype of your ideas
should an inspection be requested.
(Cobuild corpus, UK magazines)
(11) … and I think it is absolutely critical that we should be devoting our attention er, to policing that catches criminals and prevents crime … 
(BNC, spoken discourse)
(12) a.Yes, interesting you should say that, because the definition I
had was something quite the reverse.
(BNC, spoken discourse)

b.It is so cruel that such a thing should happen to such a nice,
normal family. 
(Cobuild corpus, Sun newspaper)

c.It may be coincidence that you should choose to write to me
now when what you dearly want is within reach.
(Cobuild corpus, Sun newspaper)

d.That Oxford and Cambridge should be capable of sustaining
such a profile in the professional era is to the credit of those
who run the university clubs.
(Cobuild corpus, Times newspaper)
(13) So the point of conclusion is if the myth is different in the
Bible then the likely explanation is that it was tampered with,
but that the scribes and the people who wrote the Bible altered
the … and they changed it round why should they change this

(BNC, spoken discourse)
myth? 


The reason why such sentences were excluded is that we only wanted to
find factors which favour the choice for should or ought to in sentences in
which they both could in principle occur. In (9a-d), should is used as an

10.7.26 11:52:16 AM


104

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

alternative to would after the subject I. In (10a, b), should is used in a
conditional clause to add a sense of tentativeness, i.e. to suggest that the
speaker doesn’t think the actualisation of the situation is highly likely. In
(11), should is used in a that-clause depending on an expression of necessity. In this sentence should alternates with the present (‘mandative’)
subjunctive. However, we did include most of the sentences in which the
modal occurs in a that-clause complementing an expression of suggestion,
advice and even occasionally necessity, since we can observe that ought
to is not wholly excluded from such contexts (although grammars do not
record this usage):
(14) a.Indeed by this time Mao is specifically advocating that the
Party ought to take a more cautious and less radical approach to land reform so as to not antagonize the interests of
the middle and rich peasants. 
(BNC, spoken discourse)


b.It almost seems unfair to require that the computer ought to
be able to do things that the programmer has not foreseen.
( />In (12) above, should is used in content clauses occurring with expressions indicating a (typically emotion-fuelled) personal opinion. In such
sentences an indicative form could generally be used instead of should,
but by using should, the speaker indicates that he considers the mere idea
of something as surprising or remarkable. A somewhat related use concerns should after why to suggest that the speaker can’t see any obvious
reason for actualisation of the situation; cf. (13), where ought to would
have been odd. Yet, most sentences with why were retained since, again,
it can be found that ought to is not completely impossible in this context,
in so far as failing to see a reason for something is often tantamount to
failing to see a (deontic or epistemic) need or necessity for it:
(15) a.There is absolutely no reason why film technicians ought to
be expected to work for less than, say, a shelf stacker in a
supermarket… 
(shootingpeople.org/poll/minimumwage/)

distinctions.indd 104-105



105

b. I don’t see why it ought to be a high turnout election.
(Corpus of Contemporary American English)

The purification of our corpus examples resulted in an actual data set of
461 examples with should and 494 examples with ought to. As can be
inferred from the above discussion, deciding whether an example should
be expunged or retained was not always an easy matter. We have been as

conservative as possible, thus leaving in perhaps more examples than other researchers would have done. All in all, we do not think this jeopardises the replicability of our study.

3.2.  Parameters Investigated in This Study
To the best of our knowledge, this paper investigates the potential impact of the largest number of parameters (i.e. variables) ever considered in
the comparison of two modal verbs. These are listed below, grouped for
convenience by a few headings (but different groupings are of course possible).
Semantic parameters:
—deontic vs. epistemic vs. merger
—subjective (stance-taking) vs. objective (no stance-taking)
—past-time reference (modality is situated in the past) vs. no pasttime reference
Properties of the subject:
—1st vs. 2nd vs. 3rd person
—animate vs. inanimate
—agentive (subject control over action) vs. non-agentive (lack of
subject control)
Properties of the verb following the modal:
—dynamic vs. stative
—present tense vs. perfect tense
perfect: contracted (’ve, sometimes spelled of) vs. non‌contracted
—simple vs. progressive
—active vs. passive

10.7.26 11:52:16 AM


106

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Syntactic properties of the clause:

—code (use of modal to substitute entire VP, e.g. You should!) vs.
no code
—extraposition of the subject (e.g. It should be noted that…) vs.
no extraposition
—position of an adverb (if there is one) before (e.g. You really
ought to…) vs. after the modal (You should really…)
—clause type: embedded by think or a similar expression of cognition (assume, believe, feel, it seems to me, …)
—clause type: embedded by suggest or a related item (advocate,
advise, argue, consult, insist, legislate, recommend, request,
require, persuade, stipulate, etc.; also nouns like suggestion/
proposal (that) and periphrastic constructions like think it
wise (that) and it is appropriate/essential (that))
—polarity: positive vs. negative
—negation: external (e.g. You shouldn’t be frightened = ‘It’s
not necessary to be frightened’) vs. internal (e.g. This privilege should not be abused = ‘It is necessary not to abuse
this privilege’)
—negation: contracted (-n’t) vs. non-contracted
—negation: negative raising (e.g. I don’t think you ought to
say that) vs. otherwise
—negation: negative subject (e.g. No marriage ought to be
contracted on this day) vs. otherwise
—negation: near-negative (e.g. We should only…) vs. otherwise
—declarative vs. interrogative (including dependent questions, e.g.
[boys who worry about] what moisturiser they should be using)
—introduced by why (or a covert form, as in There’s no reason
_ teenagers shouldn’t earn pocket money) vs. otherwise
—subject-operator inversion vs. no subject-operator inversion
—coordination of modals (e.g. What the trial judge can and
should do…) vs. no coordination of modals


distinctions.indd 106-107

Should vs. Ought to

107

—(only for ought to) do-support vs. absence of do-support
—(only for ought to) infinitive marker to vs. reduced (oughta) vs.
absent
The quantitative results for these individual parameters are provided in
the tables presented as addenda. Remember, however, that the primary
aim of this study is to discover which factors have a unique contribution
to the selection of should vs. ought to. Perhaps paradoxically, this can
only be achieved by considering all the parameters together: only then can
we know whether a parameter has a unique impact or whether it has to be
disregarded because its effect correlates strongly to that of another parameter whose impact is stronger (and which should therefore be retained, unless it in turn correlates with a yet stronger parameter). Exactly how such
a multivariate analysis proceeds is explained in the next subsection.
One additional semantic parameter (‘counterfactuality’) was later on assembled on the basis of two of the above parameters: if the verb following the modal was either a full perfect auxiliary or the progressive auxiliary be, the modality was considered to convey counterfactuality (non‌fulfilment); otherwise it was not. For a motivation of this operationalisation, see section 2.2, but see also section 5 for further discussion. The
reason why only full perfect auxiliaries but not contracted ones were assigned the value ‘counterfactual’ was that we knew, at the time we assembled this variable, that contracted perfect auxiliaries occur significantly
more frequently after should than after ought to, while we suspected, on
the basis of the linguistic literature, that a suggestion of non-fulfilment occurs especially frequently with ought to. If we had included contracted
auxiliaries in the set of ‘counterfactual’ examples, a possible impact of
counterfactuality on the choice of should vs. ought to would therefore
have been harder to detect, because it might have been cancelled out by
the impact of contracted auxiliaries. The parameter ‘aspect’ (simple vs.
progressive infinitive after the modal auxiliary) was removed from the
analysis after assembling the parameter ‘counterfactuality,’ and the parameter ‘tense’ then acquired a purely morpho-phonological interpretation
(presence or absence of a reduced perfect auxiliary).

10.7.26 11:52:16 AM



108

3.3.  Methodology
In order to find out which of the parameters mentioned above contributes significantly to the should/ought to variation in English, we fitted a
so-called logistic regression model. This technique, which is very popular
in sociolinguistic circles (cf. Goldvarb; Sankoff, Tagliamonte and Smith
(2005)), is a multivariate analysis method that measures the simultaneous
effect of one or more parameters, which may be categorical and continuous in nature, on a binary outcome (in this case should vs. ought to). By
means of such a multivariate technique, significant variables can be distinguished from non-significant ones and the relative impact of each of the
significant variables is estimated (i.e. the impact of parameter X while
controlling for the effects of all other parameters included in the model). 
Finally, such techniques can yield insight into the descriptive, explanatory
and predictive power of the resulting model (i.e., to what extent can the
observed variation be described, explained and predicted by the explanatory variables). The statistical package R 2.7.0 (R Development Core
Team (2008)) was used to conduct this statistical analysis.
Before presenting the results of the logistic regression model, some remarks have to be made. First, for technical reasons, we reorganised parameters with more than two values, as well as parameters where one of
the two values led to one or more further distinctions, to single-level, binary parameters. In doing so, we grouped those values together which
had a similar effect on the should/ought to variation, or to put it somewhat
differently, which maximised the difference between the values of the
non-binary parameters. Thus, for the parameter polarity, we decided to
regroup the values such that each sentence could be assigned either of two
values: (i) negative polarity with the negation marked on the modal auxiliary (i.e. should not / ought not to / shouldn’t / oughtn’t to) or (ii) positive
polarity or negative polarity which is not marked on the modal auxiliary. 
Second, we did not include any interaction effects in the model, since preparatory analyses pointed out that such a model is corrupted by multicollinearity. More particularly, the estimates of the interaction terms correlated heavily with the main terms, as a consequence of which the estimates became unstable. Third, some of the parameters mentioned in the

distinctions.indd 108-109

Should vs. Ought to


Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

109

previous section had to be removed from the model, as preparatory analyses revealed that their effect correlated heavily with the effect of other parameters (yielding a new multicollinearity problem). In particular, the parameters animacy, agentivity, dynamicity, sentence type (declarative vs.
interrogative), voice (active vs. passive) and presence of why were excluded for that reason. For instance, the parameter sentence type correlated
with inversion, and the parameter voice (active vs. passive) correlated
with agentivity, which correlated with meaning (deontic vs. epistemic or
merger) and with animacy, which in turn also correlated with person. In
choosing which of the correlating parameters should be retained, we opted
for the parameters with the strongest effect on the variation at hand. This
way, we ensured that the resulting model of the should/ought to variation
only contained parameters with a unique impact on the variation and no
parameters whose effect is redundant to that of another parameter.

4.  Results
Our statistical model, made up of 14 non-correlating parameters, fits the
data well (p = 0.14). This means that there is no reason to assume that
there is a discrepancy between the variation accounted for by the model
and the actual (observed) variation. The model’s predictive power, however, is rather low (c = 0.69, a value closer to 0.5 (no predictive accuracy)
than to 1 (full predictive accuracy)). Table 2 provides an overview of the
retained parameters, ordered by individual strength (as expressed by the
odds ratio).
Starting from the base-line expectation that should and ought to have an
a priori equal chance of being selected (i.e., controlling for the overall
higher frequency of should compared to ought to noted in section 3.1), we
can read the results in Table 2 as follows.
First, in sentences with inversion between the subject and the operator
(e.g. {Should we / Ought we to} do that?), should is more than twelve

times as likely to be selected compared to when there is no inversion. 
This effect is highly significant.
Second, when the word following the modal is a contracted perfect

10.7.26 11:52:16 AM


110

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Parameter and Its Setting for Selection of Should

Subject-operator inversion: yes
Following word: ’ve
Adverb: none or right after the auxiliary
Polarity: verb-marked negative
Modal proposition embedded by an item like suggest: yes
Past-time reference: no
Modal proposition embedded by a cognition item: no
Person of the subject: third
Meaning: epistemic or merger
Counterfactual: no
Subjective: yes
Code: yes
Extraposition: yes
Coordination of modals: yes


Odds Ratio Significance
12.6
10
3.9
2.9
2.7
2.2
2.1
1.9
n.a.
n.a.
n.a.
n.a.
n.a.
n.a.

***
***
*
***
**
***
***
***
n.s.
n.s.
n.s.
n.s.
n.s.
n.s.


Table 2: S
 tatistical Model of the Variation between Should and Ought
to, with Predictors for should, Odds Ratios and Significance
Levels (‘***’: p < 0.001; ‘**’: p < 0.01; ‘*’: p < 0.05; ‘n.s.’:
not significant); ‘n.a.’ = not applicable
auxiliary (’ve, sometimes spelled of, as in You {should / ought to} {’ve /
of} told me), the likelihood of that modal being should is ten times higher
than when the following word is not a contracted perfect auxiliary. This
effect is highly significant.
Third, when there is no adverb or when it is positioned between the
(verbal part of the) modal and the to-infinitive (as in You {should probably
/ ought probably to} ignore this), that modal is almost four times as likely
to be should compared to when there is an adverb before the modal (as in
You probably {should / ought to} ignore this), in which case of course the
likelihood of that modal being ought to is more than four times as likely
(compared to when there is no adverb or an adverb right before the to‌infinitive). This effect is significant at the 0.05 level.
Fourth, when the polarity is negative and expressed by means of not
or -n’t following the (verbal part of the) modal (as in We {shouldn’t /
oughtn’t to} do this), that modal is almost three times as likely to be

distinctions.indd 110-111

111

should compared to when the modality is positive (as in We {should /
ought to} do that) or negative without the negation being marked directly
on the modal (as in I don’t think we {should / ought to} do that). This effect is highly significant.
Fifth, when the modal proposition is a complement of suggest or a similar expression of suggestion, advisability, etc., should is almost three
times as likely to be selected compared to when the modal proposition is

not embedded by such an item. This effect is significant at the 0.01 level.
Sixth, when there is no past time reference (as in Listen to me, you
{should / ought to} get some tests done), should is more than twice as
likely to be selected compared to when there is past-time reference, as is
the case in the corpus sentence Then my father told me I ought to get
some tests done and the polyps were diagnosed (Cobuild corpus, Today
newspaper). This effect is highly significant.
Seventh, when the modal proposition is not a complement of think or a
similar expression of cognition, should is more than twice as likely to be
selected compared to when the proposition is embedded by such an item
(as in I think you {should / ought to} give it a try). This effect is highly
significant.
Eighth, when the subject of the modal proposition is a third person (as
in He {should / ought to} apologise), should is almost twice as likely to
be selected compared to when the subject is a first or a second person (as
in {I / you / we} {should / ought to} apologise). This effect is highly significant.
All other parameters are not significant—notably, this is the case for
meaning (epistemicity/merger vs. deonticity) and for counterfactuality—or
were left out of the model because they correlated with one or more of
the other parameters.

5.  Discussion
Our model of the unique factors governing the choice between should
and ought to allows us to describe this variation fairly parsimoniously in
terms of eight significant factors and six more factors whose impact turns

10.7.26 11:52:17 AM


112


Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

out not to be significant. We have managed to rank the relevant factors
according to their relative strength. This is a major descriptive advance
with respect to previous studies.
Our statistical model also allows us to explain some of the variation in
terms of the intrinsic formal difference between should and ought to. The
four strongest factors can all be linked to the fact that should is a standard
modal auxiliary verb whereas ought to is, in fact, only a semi-modal verb,
as appears from the fact that it (standardly) cannot take a bare infinitive. 
Ought to has therefore been described as a blend between a true modal
and a full, lexical verb. As a concomitant of its hybrid status, we encounter it least frequently in structures where we do not normally find full
verbs: inversion (e.g. Ought you to go?, cp. *Like you to go?), addition of
a reduced auxiliary (e.g. We ought to’ve gone, cp. *We would have liked
to’ve gone), insertion of an adverb (e.g. You ought probably to go, cp.
*You like probably to go) and verb-marked negation (e.g. We ought not to
go, cp. *We like not to go). That a contracted perfect auxiliary (’ve instead of have) is avoided strongly with ought to, as with other verbs taking a to-infinitive, is because to is itself phonologically weak and in that
respect a dispreferred attachment site for another reduced item (compare
also I won’t / I haven’t, where the reduced negator attaches to phonologically strong material, and *I’lln’t / *I’ven’t, where it does not).
At first sight, there may be not much reason for being euphoric about
the predictive accuracy of our statistical model. The C-value of our model is 0.69, but this is a correlation value, so one should not interpret this
in terms of a fraction (i.e., it doesn’t mean that the model would manage
to correctly guess the identity of ‘masked’ modals in our set in over two
thirds of the cases). Note, indeed, that the C-value always gives a score
between 0.5 and 1. A value of 0.5 would mean that there is no correlation at all between the actual choice between should and ought to in our
set of examples and the choice of the modal auxiliary that the model
would ‘predict’ on the basis of the specific values each example has for
the factors included in the model. A value of 1 would mean that there is
full correlation between actual and predicted choice of modal auxiliary. 

Clearly, while the C-value of our model is removed from the 0.5 bottom

distinctions.indd 112-113

Should vs. Ought to

113

score, there is much room for improvement, and some claim that only
from a 0.8 score onwards can one conclude that a statistical model has
sufficient stability.
The fact that our model has rather low predictive power can be interpreted in two different ways. One way is to refer to the received opinion
about should and ought to, which is that they are highly synonymous (cf.
section 1). Any model which yielded a C-value which is rather higher
than 0.5 should therefore be considered as a triumph over the view that
there is no clear distinction between should and ought to and that there is
free variation between them. Perhaps a higher score can’t be reached, no
matter how hard one looked for extra determining factors. Language allows for some variation, which means speakers can in some usage situations choose between multiple options. Even if one could find factors
which heighten the likelihood of a particular option in given circum­
stances, there might always be cases where speakers act against the odds,
for no apparent reason (cf. Cappelle (2009)).
Another view is that the fairly low C-value suggests that not all relevant factors have been found and/or that the factors may not have been
optimally operationalised. For instance, we might refine our operationalisation of the factor non-fulfilment (cf. section 2.2) since a perfect infinitive only suggests nonactualisation if the use of the modal is deontic. As
Declerck (1991: 411) rightly points out, a sentence like (16) is ambiguous:
(16) It’s two o’clock. The train should have crossed the border by
now.
(after Declerck (1991: 411))
This sentence could be interpreted as ‘Given the time, I expect that the
train has crossed the border,’ with the perfect infinitive expressing anteriority to the time of speech. However, it could also be read as ‘Given the
time, it’s not normal that the train hasn’t crossed the border yet (damn this

unreliable railway company).’ Even with deontic uses, there need not
be an implication of nonactualisation (Declerck (1991: 379); cf. also
Huddleston and Pullum (2002: 204)):
(17) To be eligible for the post you should have worked for the firm

10.7.26 11:52:17 AM


114

for at least ten years.

(Declerck (1991: 379))

Similarly, a progressive infinitive does not suggest nonactualisation if the
use of the modal is epistemic. Consider (17):
(18)  The students should be studying hard now.
If should is epistemic, the interpretation is something like ‘(given the time
of year,) we can only conclude that the students are studying hard now,’
with no suggestion that this is not the case (although the speaker is more
tentative in his conclusion than if he had used must). Only if should is
used deontically do we (automatically) get the interpretation that the students are not, in fact, studying hard now. In the light of these complications, we might have to admit that our operationalisation of the potential
factor ‘suggestion of non-fulfilment’ was not very adequate and that a better operationalisation might have yielded better results.
After all, there is some evidence that ought might indeed be preferred if
the speaker does not want to imply that the (deontic) necessity actually
has to be fulfilled. Consider an utterance like (19):
(19) Whoever perpetuated the bare-belly look ought to be hanged.
(BNC, written discourse)
Here, there is no suggestion that the subject should actually be prosecuted
and punished with death by hanging. At most, the author suggests that in

an ‘ideal’ world where one could inflict horrible punishments at will and
on a whim, this would be the course of action he’d suggest—all the while
acknowledging that this is not something one could realistically ask for in
the real world. In the Corpus of Contemporary American English, we
searched for the modals should and ought to followed by be and a past
participle. From the list of past participles, we selected 10 verbs referring
to situations whose likelihood of realisation is low or nonexistent and 10
verbs referring to situations that are more likely to be realised. The results are given in Table 3. The distribution is highly significant (χ2 =
44.4, d.f. = 1, p < 0.001).

distinctions.indd 114-115

115

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Unlikely Situations
(fired / shot / killed / castrated / euthanized /
exiled / horsewhipped / hanged / bombed /
crucified)
Likely Situations
(considered / treated / called / encouraged /
regarded / pointed [incl. pointed out] / interpreted / recognized / emphasized / avoided)

Should Be… Ought to Be…
  213

  32


3318

135

Table 3: D
 istribution of Should Be and Ought to Be before Past
Participles Referring to Likely and Unlikely Situations in the
Corpus of Contemporary American English
This remarkable difference between should and ought to might also be
due in part by a difference in formality between the verbs involved—remember that ought to has a higher likelihood of occurrence in informal
than in formal discourse. Furthermore, it may be suspected that the first
group of verbs would come up more naturally in discourse in which the
speaker expressed his personal views than in discourse where the speaker
is less personally (and emotionally) involved.
This brings us to the issue of subjectivity vs. objectivity, which
Declerck (1991) and others have related the choice of should and ought
to, the latter being claimed to be more objective than the former (cf. section 2.1). In the remainder of this section, we will discuss this parameter
in some detail. We are not convinced that should is more subjective than
ought to. In fact, we see three counter-indications, dealt with in the next
three subsections. A more fundamental problem of the subjectivity/objectivity distinction is then discussed in 5.4.

5.1.  Corpus Evidence against Ought to as Being “More Objective”
Our corpus contained few instances in which the speaker expresses an
‘objective’ opinion (as in (1a) above)—and besides, whether an opinion
counts as truly objective is always hard to verify—or in which the speaker
just plainly states which requirements ‘objectively’ have to be fulfilled for

10.7.26 11:52:17 AM



116

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

some other situation (as in (1b) above). At any rate, we did not find corroboration that ought to occurs more frequently than should in such cases.
However, if ought to were really more objective than should, then it
should be avoided in contexts containing hedges like I think or If you ask
me, but sentences like the following do occur, seem perfectly natural and
have been shown in this study to be indeed more frequent than similar
sentences with should (cf. the seventh result stated in section 4).
(20) a.If you ask me, though, it ought to be twice that size.
(www.deadline.com/hollywood/mr-rogers-gone-but-notforgotten/)

b.“I think this woman ought to be replaced immediately by
myself,” he said.
(Cobuild corpus, The Times newspaper)

c.…what’s been er been going through my head recently is,
is er the, looking at the pattern of the meetings and the way
the meetings are arranged and, and how, erm, at the last
meeting we had a speaker er and that I think, we all found
that quite interesting and the one, one from Central America
that things and I feel we ought to have that much more frequently than we do have er, a, either a speaker or a focus of
some sort of meetings erm, so I think that’s something I’d
like to raise and get the A G M at the next meeting I think
[a] similar thing we ought to consider there…
(BNC, spoken discourse)

Moreover, our study also reveals that ought to (vs. should) is chosen
twice as likely with first and second person subjects, which refer to the
author and his addressee, as with third person subjects (cf. our eighth result). This suggests that ought to is more (inter)subjective than should.

5.2.  Should is Not Necessarily Speaker-grounded
It is not hard to find examples similar to those which Declerck (1991)
claims should sound odd:
(21) a. I should probably apologise… But I won’t.

distinctions.indd 116-117



117

(losingit.me.uk/2009/08/21/i-should-probably-apologise)
b. I know I should shut up now, but I won’t.
( />
One might try to save the subjective value of should by proposing that
should more generally refers to someone’s subjective view, whether this
view can be attributed to the speaker/writer or to someone else. It could
indeed be argued that in (21a, b) should is not used to give advice to oneself but to represent an obligation or advice which arises outside the
speaker/writer—these sentences are in this respect not altogether different
from cases of ‘distancing indirect speech/thought’; cf. Vandelanotte (this
volume and the references presented there). For instance, (21a) might be
seen as a shortened version of ‘Some people would probably give me the
advice that I should apologise…’ and (21b) might be equivalent to ‘I
know that you think I should shut up now….’
However, if the necessity expressed by should happens to be speaker/
writer-external, it still need not be a subjective necessity. Consider (22):

(22)I should be fasting for Ramadan but I won’t today—­­maybe tomorrow.
(www.telegraph.co.uk/.../How-money-stopped-mattering-forDragons-Den-mogul-James-Caan.html)
Again, the necessity in this sentence isn’t grounded in the writer. The
sentence wouldn’t differ noticeably in its interpretation from “According
to the Koran, I should be fasting for Ramadan....” But a course of action
prescribed by the Koran can hardly be considered as a necessity based on
a subjective view.

5.3.  When No Stance Is Taken, Ought to Cannot Be Used
For ‘objective’ requirements as can be found in official letters, instruction booklets, public notices and so on, it is actually should, but not ought
to, which can be used (cf. Close (1981: 120-122), Westney (1995: 172)):
(23) a.Applications should be submitted by March 31st at the latest.

(Close (1981: 120))

10.7.26 11:52:17 AM


118

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter





b. Entries should be clearly typed. 
(Gailor (1983: 348))
c.Carbon knives should be wiped clean after use. (from a
written instruction)

(Westney (1995: 166))
d.This coffee-machine should be turned off after use. (from a
printed public notice)
(Westney (1995: 172))

It may be the case that degree of formality plays a role here, too (cf. section 4). Yet, the relatively high formality of these utterances cannot be
invoked as the sole reason why ought to would be odd here, since this
modal is otherwise definitely not excluded from writing. Still another parameter, namely implication of fulfilment vs. non-fulfilment, discussed
above and in section 3.2, might be at work here. Take, for instance,
(23a): it would be very awkward to state that applications must be submitted by a specified date while implying that this requirement might not be
met. Whichever additional factors may or may not play a role, though,
the above examples prove wrong Swan’s (1980: 550) and Declerck’s
(1991: 377, fn. 21) claim that ought to is the modal to be used for talking
about laws, duties and regulations.
We believe that ought to is in fact excluded in decrees, official rules,
guidelines, etc., which do not involve stance-taking, that is, where the utterances do not express someone’s personal opinions (whether it be the
speaker/writer’s or someone else’s) but merely form statements of procedures to be followed.

5.4.  Other Issues with Subjectivity vs. Objectivity
Both should and ought to are claimed by Declerck (1991: 377-378) to
“merely express a moral obligation (rather than an objective necessity)”
(our emphasis). But if should and ought to already differ from each other
in terms of whether the obligation expressed is based on a subjective
opinion or something more objective, how can one then go on to claim
that should and ought to as a pair differ from other deontic modals, such
as must and have (got) to, in exactly those terms? We are forced to conclude that the distinction ‘subjective’ vs. ­­­­­­‘objective’ is too coarse to differentiate all deontic modals. (We are leaving epistemic modals out of the

distinctions.indd 118-119

Should vs. Ought to


119

picture here, since Declerck (1991) doesn’t discuss the difference between
epistemic should or ought to on the one hand and must on the other in
terms of subjectivity but in terms of tentativeness.)
If taken as a cline, subjectivity might be more adequate (as in Degani
(2009: 334)). This is, in fact, how Declerck apparently looks at this parameter (cf. “ought to is more objective”; our emphasis). But then subjectivity also becomes rather impractical as a variable when it comes to
judging individual examples: on what basis can we (objectively) decide
for any two instances whether they are equally subjective/objective or
whether one of them is more subjective/objective than the other?
This problem does not apply to Collins’s claim quoted in section 2.1
(“the proportion of objective cases is higher with ought to”), from which
we can infer that he doesn’t consider subjectivity itself to be scalar. 
Rather, he allows deontic modals to be ranked according to this binary
criterion, on the basis of how many instances of each modal qualify as
‘subjective.’ On the other hand, with a two-way distinction, there may be
many cases where there is doubt whether the example should be classified
as subjective or objective, and where a middle category might therefore
have been helpful.
The parameter ‘modality embedded by a cognition expression’ which
we used in our study might perhaps be considered the most objective approximation variable (‘proxy’) of subjectivity and it is also in accordance
with the desideratum that other modals can be ranked with respect to it.

6.  Some Further Observations
In this section we will focus on some interesting examples that we
came across when coding the corpus data. These examples have no immediate bearing on the main findings of this study but are worth discussing in a study on should and ought to.

6.1.  Didn’t as Tag after Ought to
The following example is curious in that it shows that ought to cannot

only be felt to be more like a full verb than a modal auxiliary, hence the

10.7.26 11:52:17 AM


120

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

use of do-support, but also in that it appears to be thought of as a past
tense form—which, historically, it is:
(24) Right! Your school ju, your school jumper ought to be cleaned
(BNC, spoken discourse)
didn’t it?
This example might perhaps more naturally be explained as a case of free
indirect speech, i.e. with an understood They said or You said, in which
case ought to can be interpreted as having past time reference. As our
study revealed, past time reference is a frequent option with ought to.

6.2.  Should + Have to
Unlike ought to, should is occasionally combined with deontic have to,
a possibility noted by Harris (1986) (cf. also Kennedy (2002)). We have
found a single instance in our corpus:
(25) We should only have to look as far back as a season or at the
most a couple. 
(Cobuild corpus, Sun newspaper)
This apparently redundant addition of have to is probably most common
with Why should…, where the basic deontic interpretation of should is

bleached (cf. the discussion of (13) in section 3.1). In the BNC, 27 hits
are returned for the sequence “why should * have to.”

6.3.  E
 pistemic Should / Ought to and Situations Expressing a
Positive Idea
A little-observed property of epistemic should and ought to, which they
do not share with epistemic must, is that they can seemingly only be used
for situations which are felt to be positive rather than negative (cf. Quirk
et al. (1985: 227), Westney (1995: 179)). This property has intrigued
Renaat Declerck, to whom the following examples are due:
(26) a.It {should / ought to} be {easy / *difficult} to solve that
problem.—That problem {shouldn’t / oughtn’t} to be {*easy
/ difficult} to solve.

b.It must be {easy / difficult} to solve that problem.—That

distinctions.indd 120-121

121

problem can’t be {easy / difficult} to solve.
We cannot go into the hypothesis Declerck has offered in a working document to explain this contrast. Instead, let us consider the following extended corpus extract, which at first sight would seem to constitute a
counterexample:
(27) “Not surprisingly, against this background, consumer and business confidence is still deteriorating,” the Oxford group said. 
Oxford said that interest rates in both Europe and America
should fall further, predicting 2.75 per cent rates in Germany
by the spring and 4.75 per cent in the US by the summer. Most
other countries would follow suit. Lower interest rates would
bolster growth, it added.

(Cobuild corpus, Times newspaper)
Note, however, that the last sentence reveals that the situation of falling
further is not necessarily bad.

7.  Conclusions
This corpus-based study on should and ought to in contemporary spoken and written British English usage has shown that these two near-synonymous modals are not identical in use. The data confirmed previous
observations that should is used much more frequently than ought to and
that the frequency of ought to in spoken language is higher than its frequency in written language.
Out of many more investigated parameters, eight were shown to exert a
unique and significant impact on the choice of should vs. ought to, in order of decreasing strength: (i) inversion, (ii) a following contracted perfect
infinitive, (iii) a following adverb (or none), (iv) negation, (v) embedding
by suggest or a similar item, (vi) reference to the non-past, (vii) no embedding by think or a similar cognition expression and (viii) third (vs. first
or second) person subject. The four strongest parameters can be linked to
the fact that should is a member of the set of core modal auxiliaries while
ought to is, morpho-syntactically speaking, only a so-called semi-modal or

10.7.26 11:52:18 AM


122

quasi-modal. While ought to does have the NICE properties (allowing
negation, inversion, code and emphasis without do-support), it tends to be
avoided precisely in environments where it has to display auxiliary-like
properties.
We have also provided evidence, pace Declerck (1991) and some other
scholars, against statements that should is more subjective than ought to. 
If anything, the contrary appears to be the case.

Meaning


Subjectivity
Time reference

Deontic
Epistemic
Merger
Subjective
Objective
Non-past
Past

Ought to
Written
Spoken
200 (79%) 225 (94%)
  35 (14%)    9 (4%)
  19 (8%)    6 (3%)
240 (95%) 236 (98%)
  14 (6%)    4 (2%)
173 (68%) 224 (93%)
  81 (32%)   16 (7%)

Table A1: Distribution of Should and Ought to by Semantic Factors

Person

Animacy
Agentivity


Should
Written
Spoken
1st
  21 (9%)   58 (26%)
2nd
  21 (9%)   42 (19%)
3rd
200 (83%) 114 (52%)
Animate
145 (60%) 149 (68%)
Inanimate
  97 (40%)   70 (32%)
Agentive
112 (46%) 103 (47%)
Nonagentive 130 (54%) 116 (53%)

Ought to
Written
Spoken
  49 (19%)   95 (40%)
  23 (9%)   45 (19%)
182 (72%)   96 (40%)
156 (61%) 198 (83%)
  98 (39%)   40 (17%)
102 (40%) 148 (62%)
152 (60%)   92 (38%)

Table A2: D
 istribution of Should and Ought to by Properties of the

Subject

distinctions.indd 122-123

Dynamicity
Tense

Dynamic

Stative

Present

Perfect

Written

Should

Spoken

Voice

Full

Simple

Progressive

Active


Passive

Written

Ought to

Spoken

166 (69%) 122 (56%) 152 (60%) 158 (66%)

  76 (32%)   97 (44%) 102 (40%)   82 (34%)

219 (91%) 197 (90%) 219 (86%) 226 (94%)

  23 (10%)   22 (10%)   35 (14%)   14 (6%)

Contracted    1 (0%)

Aspect

Appendices
Should
Written
Spoken
195 (81%) 183 (84%)
  34 (14%)   15 (7%)
  13 (5%)   21 (10%)
227 (94%) 206 (94%)
  15 (6%)   13 (6%)

216 (89%) 197 (90%)
  26 (11%)   22 (10%)

123

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

  22 (9%)

   8 (4%)
  14 (6%)

   0 (0%)

   2 (1%)

  35 (14%)   12 (5%)

232 (97%) 203 (93%) 240 (94%) 220 (92%)

  10 (4%)

  16 (7%)

  14 (6%)

  20 (8%)


194 (81%) 197 (90%) 211 (83%) 221 (92%)

  48 (20%)   22 (10%)   43 (17%)   19 (8%)

Table A3: D
 istribution of Should and Ought to by Properties of the
Infinitive

Code
Extraposed
Subject
Position of
Adverb

Yes

No

Yes

No

Before modal

After modal

Embedded by Yes
think-clause
No


Embedded by Yes
suggest-clause No

Polarity

Positive

Written

Should

Spoken

Written

Ought to

Spoken

   3 (1%)

   9 (4%)

   5 (2%)

   8 (3%)

   7 (3%)

   5 (2%)


   5 (2%)

   8 (3%)

   3 (1%)

   2 (1%)

   8 (3%)

  13 (5%)

239 (100%) 210 (96%) 249 (98%) 232 (97%)

235 (98%) 214 (98%) 249 (98%) 232 (97%)

  20 (8%)
   5 (2%)

  12 (5%)

  12 (5%)

   3 (1%)

  32 (15%)   38 (15%)   54 (23%)

237 (99%) 187 (85%) 216 (85%) 186 (78%)


  17 (7%)

  16 (7%)

   4 (2%)

   9 (4%)

225 (94%) 203 (93%) 250 (98%) 231 (96%)

216 (90%) 183 (84%) 236 (93%) 228 (95%)

10.7.26 11:52:18 AM


124

Negative
Internal
External
Contracted
Raising
Neg. subject
Near-neg.

Sentence type

Declarative

Interrogative


Introduced by Yes
why
No

Inversion

Coordination
of modals
Do-support
Infinitive
marker

Should vs. Ought to

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

Yes

No

Yes

No

Yes

No

to


Reduced
Absent

  26
  24
   2
   8
   0
   2
   2

(11%)
(10%)
(1%)
(3%)
(0%)
(1%)
(1%)

  36
  31
   5
  21
   5
   2
   1

(16%)
(14%)

(2%)
(10%)
(2%)
(1%)
(0%)

  18
  14
   4
   4
   2
   4
   0

(7%)
(6%)
(2%)
(2%)
(1%)
(2%)
(0%)

  12 (5%)
  11 (5%)
   1 (0%)
   1 (0%)
   5 (2%)
   0 (0%)
   0 (0%)


211 (88%) 199 (91%)    8 (3%)

224 (93%)

   8 (3%)

   7 (3%)

   0 (0%)

   1 (0%)

  12 (5%)

  12 (5%)

   2 (1%)

   0 (0%)

   4 (2%)

   0 (0%)

   4 (2%)

   0 (0%)

   0 (0%)


   1 (0%)

  31 (13%)   20 (9%)

246 (97%)   16 (7%)

234 (98%) 212 (97%) 254 (100%) 239 (100%)

230 (96%) 207 (95%) 252 (99%) 240 (100%)

238 (99%) 219 (100%) 250 (98%) 240 (100%)

n.a.

n.a.

n.a.

n.a.
n.a.

n.a.

n.a.

n.a.

n.a.
n.a.


254 (100%) 239 (100%)

249 (98%) 236 (98%)

   2 (1%)
   3 (1%)

   1 (0%)
   3 (1%)

Table A4: D
 istribution of Should and Ought to by Syntactic Properties
of the Clause (Note: ‘n.a.’ = not applicable)
References
Aarts, Flor and Herman Wekker (1987) A Contrastive Grammar of English and
Dutch, Martinus Nijhoff, Leiden.
Cappelle, Bert (2009) “Can We Factor Out Free Choice?” Describing and
Modeling Variation in Grammar, ed. by Dufter, Andreas, Jürg Fleischer and
Guido Seiler, 183-202, Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin and New York.
Celce-Murcia, Marianne and Diane Larsen-Freeman (1983) The Grammar Book:
An ESL/EFL Teacher’s Course, Newbury House, Rowley, MA.
Close, Reginald A. (1981) English as a Foreign Language: Its Constant

distinctions.indd 124-125

125

Grammatical Problems, 3rd ed., George Allen & Unwin, London.
Coates, Jennifer (1983) The Semantics of the Modal Auxiliaries, Croom Helm,
London and Canberra.

Collins, Peter (2009) Modals and Quasi-Modals in English, Rodopi, Amsterdam
and New York.
Declerck, Renaat (1991) A Comprehensive Descriptive Grammar of English,
Kaitakusha, Tokyo.
Degani, Marta (2009) “Re-analysing the Semi-Modal Ought to: An Investigation
of Its Use in the LOB, FLOB, Brown and Frown Corpora,” Corpus
Linguistics: Refinements and Reassessments, ed. by Andrew Kehoe, 327-346,
Rodopi, Amsterdam.
Gailor, Denis (1983) “Reflections on Should, Ought to, and Must,” English
Language Teaching Journal 37, 346-349.
Harris, Martin (1986) “English Ought (to),” Linguistics across Historical and
Geographical Boundaries: In Honour of Jacek Fisiak on the Occasion of His
Fiftieth Birthday. Volume 1. Linguistic Theory and Historical Linguistics, ed.
by Dieter Kastovski and Aleksander Szwedek, 345-358, Mouton de Gruyter,
Berlin, New York and Amsterdam.
Huddleston, Rodney and Geoffrey K. Pullum (2002) The Cambridge Grammar of
the English Language, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Kennedy, Graeme (2002) “Variation in the Distribution of Modal Verbs in the
British National Corpus,” Using Corpora to Explore Linguistic Variation, ed.
by Randi Reppen, Susan M. Fitzmaurice and Douglas Biber, 73-90, John
Benjamins, Amsterdam and Philadelphia.
Leech, Geoffrey (2003) “Modality on the Move: The English Modal Auxiliaries
1961-1992,” Directions in Corpus Linguistics. Proceedings of the Nobel
Symposium 82, Stockholm, 4-8 August 1991, ed. by Roberta Facchinetti,
Manfred Krug and Frank Palmer, 223-240, Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin and
New York.
Myhill, John (1996) “Should and Ought: The Rise of Individually Oriented
Modality in American English,” English Language and Linguistics 1, 3-23.
Palmer, Frank Robert (1987) The English Verb, 2nd ed., Longman, London and
New York.

Palmer, Frank Robert (1990) Modality and the English Modals, 2nd ed., Longman,
London and New York.
Quirk, Randolph, Sidney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech and Jan Svartvik (1985) A
Comprehensive Grammar of the English language, Longman, London.
Perkins, Michael R. (1983) Modal Expressions in English, Pinter, London.

10.7.26 11:52:18 AM


126

Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter

R Development Core Team (2008) R: A Language and Environment for Statistical
Computing, Version 2.7.0, Vienna, R Foundation for Statistical Computing.
Sankoff, David, Sali A. Tagliamonte and Eric Smith (2005) “Goldvarb X: A
Variable Rule Application for Macintosh and Windows,” Department of
Linguistics, University of Toronto, Toronto.
Simpson, John, chief ed. (2000) Oxford English Dictionary Online, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Swan, Michael (1980) Practical English Usage, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Swan, Michael (1995) Practical English Usage, 2nd ed., Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Visser, Fredericus Theodorus (1963) An Historical Syntax of the English
Language. Part Three. First half. Syntactical Units with Two Verbs, Brill,
Leiden.
Westney Paul (1995) Modals and Periphrastics in English: An Investigation into
the Semantic Correspondence between Certain English Modal Verbs and
Their Periphrastic Equivalents, Niemeyer, Tübingen.


[Modals]

The English Comparative Modals—A Pilot Study*
Johan van der Auwera and Astrid De Wit
University of Antwerp

1.  Introduction
English has a number of modal constructions which could be called
‘comparative.’ The core examples of these comparative modals contain
an auxiliary and an adverbial of comparison. There are three subtypes,
depending on whether the adverb is a superlative (1a), a comparative (1b)
or an expression of equality (1c). Within each subtype, one can distinguish further subtypes, depending on the type of auxiliary or the type of
adverbial.
(1) a.
b.


c.



had best, ’d best
had better,’d better, better
would rather, ’d rather, had rather, should rather
would sooner, ’d sooner, had sooner, should sooner
would (just) as soon as
may (just) as well
might (just) as well

* This work was done within the ‘Grammaticalisation and (Inter)Subjectivity’ project

(Belgian Federal Government—Interuniversity Attraction Poles P6/44). Special thanks
are due to Folker Debusscher, Mariela Gonzalez Gomez, Benita Lašinytė, Adinda
Robberechts, Daniel Van Olmen, and Dirk Noël (the latter for making the penultimate
version of this paper take account of Collins (2009)).

127

distinctions.indd 126-127

10.7.26 11:52:18 AM



Tài liệu bạn tìm kiếm đã sẵn sàng tải về

Tải bản đầy đủ ngay
×